Tag Archives: Heidegger

BEYOND PERVERSION AND HYSTERIA TO RESURRECTION

There is a way that seems right to a person, but its end is the way to death. Proverbs 14:12

“ If the Spirit of him who raised Jesus from the dead dwells in you, he who raised Christ from the dead will give life to your mortal bodies also through his Spirit that dwells in you” (Romans 8:11).

Hildegard_von_Bingen_Liber_Divinorum_Operum

Slavoj Žižek, in his reading of Romans 7, finds within Paul two psychoanalytic categories, perversion and hysteria, which explain the possible orientations constituting the human Subject. Žižek’s project is largely aimed at demonstrating how every realm of human activity and thought, whether philosophy, politics, culture, or human sexuality, falls within these two orientations. The key issue for Žižek, though, is to demonstrate how Christianity itself can fail to realize the Pauline insight that identifies perversion and passes beyond it. His claim is that Anselm’s and Calvin’s respective theories of atonement, along with the Catholic and Protestant theologies that locate themselves in the closed systems of thought which Anselm and Calvin represent, are perverse.

The original question that Paul raises in Romans 7:7 has to do with confusing or equating law and sin. “Is the law sin (Rom. 7:7b)?” For Žižek (following Lacan) the question could be posed, “Is the Law the Thing?” (Seminar III, 83). Taking into account that law equals the symbolic (or the epistemological realm) and the Thing represents the real (which is not reality per se but the bedrock of the Subject), it could as well be read as, “Is the symbolic the real?” Is human language and knowing, which, according to Paul, operates according to the “law of sin and death,” adequate in and of itself to arrive at God or the ground of the ultimate Subject. Do we sin (propagating our philosophy, our world systems, our being) that grace may abound? “Certainly not!” (Rom.7:7).

Perversion – the Fusion of Knowing and Being

Perversion is fairly easy to identify. The pervert imagines that the world of language and law, or the realm of knowing (inclusive of the Hebraic notion of sex as knowing), provides direct access to Being and the power to establish Being through knowing. In Genesis 3 the original sin is to imagine that through “knowing good and evil” the Being of God (“You shall be like God”) is made accessible. Behind the screen of the law (“You shall not eat of it”) absolute knowing and ultimate pleasure are to be had. Transgression is the means of access and as Žižek describes it, the pervert somehow imagines himself to fill out or bring closure to a gap in the law by transgressively serving the law.

Perversion is a disavowal of anything lacking (a denial of castration or of death – “You shall not die”). The pervert seeks to completely establish the law within himself through a transgressive relationship to the law –sinning so as to increase grace or merging law and sin into two sides of the same coin with each side dependent upon the other. The pervert would provide himself, ultimately up to and including death, as the closure to the dialectic between sin and the law. As Anselm puts it, “death makes a gift of oneself to God.”

The sex pervert is the type of every perversion in that he would make the experience of sexual knowing the avenue to final reality. The comedian Pee-wee Herman (Paul Reubens) exposes himself in a theatre, by-passing any mundane ordinary sexual experience, to commune directly (passively) with the Big Other represented by the theatre audience. The sex pervert is one who makes sex the Thing, an end in itself as a means of achieving access to the Big Other or the Ground of the Subject.

Idolatry and corrupt sexuality are often equated in the Old Testament. In the graphic logic of the pervert, Israel is said to have “lusted after her lovers there, whose members were like those of donkeys, and whose issue was like that of horses” (Ezekiel 23:20). The idol is fashioned into a phallic symbol so big it is impossible to achieve but producing an exponential desire that results in human sacrifice. So sexual knowing as the avenue to Being is the biblical metaphor for a more basic idolatrous desire that would establish Being through knowing.

The philosophical and religious pervert, alike, make knowing the avenue to Being. Duns Scotus makes no distinction between existence and essence as it is found in finite and infinite being and thus poses a “univocity of being” which makes God’s Being accessible through the being of the world (one understanding of the analogia entis). Anselm, with his notion that he could think the greatest thought (“something than which nothing greater can be thought”) harnesses the divine name to thought and provides the technique (the technology) for achieving the divine. Anselm and Scotus concentrate on a different organ than Pee-wee but for the same end. Anselm will call it “divine satisfaction.”

Anselm transposes the perverse understanding directly onto God. God finds satisfaction in the ultimate transgression: “What ultimately makes this painful, difficult death equivalent to the sum total of all sin is that like the offence of sin itself the killing of Christ is valued by the quantity of its offensiveness” (Why a God Man (CDH) 11, 11 pp. 330 331). “Pain is required because of sin’s pleasure.” To get the “ransom price” (to use the biblical metaphor) the deed must be done – the offence committed so that that “same death destroy the sins even of those who put him to death” (as the title of CDH II puts it.) God the Father must inflict on his Son, measure for measure, the pain up to and including death, so as to balance out the pleasure of sin. This not only brings final satisfaction to God, but by closing the gap in human will, mankind is able to will rightly and become self identical – melding the dialectic of thought into the non-thought of a pure vision of God (the beatific vision). Anselm pictures his ability to carry out his cosmological and ontological arguments as arising directly from the empowerment given to him through divine satisfaction. He would satisfy himself in the manner of God and in fact his own satisfaction is that of God.

Anselm does not attach his theology to medieval law primarily from a cultural constraint. He is dealing throughout with what he takes to be a self evident or self authorizing realm (raw power) and this can ultimately be reduced to the necessity called law. He does not hesitate to identify “power” or “necessity” along with “will” as his proper subject. These “necessary” realms are interlocking, each implying the other. “. . . it is essential to have an understanding of power and necessity and will and certain other things which are so constituted that no one of them can be fully considered without the others” (CDH 1, 1, p. 266). 

Hysteria – Identity with the Law

Žižek reads Paul’s questions (“Is the law sin?” “Shall we sin that grace may abound?”) as the questioning of perversion that constitutes hysteria. Though he privileges hysteria, as with his reading of Paul, hysterical questioning involves the passage through and dialectic with perversion. The difference between perversion and hysteria is simply their different location within the dialectic. The pervert, as with Anselm and Scotus, presumes the law (the symbolic or knowing) provides passage beyond itself to Being (or life, beatific vision, Hegelian synthesis), while the hysteric suspends the closure (or passage beyond the law and symbolic) and directly identifies with the law and dialectic.

Between Anselm and Scotus, Thomas Aquinas poses the notion of the analogia entis, which he takes to be a rejection of Anselm’s ontological argument and its platonic notion of closure with the forms. Aquinas is not advocating either a univocity (on the order of Scotus) or a nihilistic equivocity, but his location between these two historically and intellectually marks him as having achieved a hysterical form of thought that amounts to a temporary suspension and dependence on the same dialectic.

Martin Heidegger, like Kant (and unlike Barth), recognizes that the ontological argument stands behind all of the arguments for God (including those of Thomas) as each is aiming at achieving the same sort of ontological difference. Aquinas only names and continues a form of thought of which he is the heir. He works with the same dialectic (identity through difference with a temporary suspension of sameness or synthesis). Hysteria, as its name implies, is an unstable compound and it naturally and easily slides into the perversion from which it arose. Thus the move from Anselm to Aquinas to Scotus traces the dialectic inherent between perversion and hysteria.

Though Heidegger dubs what he is refusing the “Onto-Theological constitution of metaphysics” he does not work out the mechanics of the ontological argument as developed by Anselm. As a result, in the estimation of Gregory Schufreider, Heidegger’s thought, in attempting to think the “nothing,” is simply the last in the line of onto-theological “rational mystics” which began with Anselm. It is not just Heidegger’s pursuit of the nothing on the order of Anselm, but his pursuit of Being as the form of knowing which Aquinas dubs knowing “that,” which implicates him in onto-theology. What he misses (and what Thomas misses) is that the mode of thinking of “that” (philosophy, philosophy of religion, rationalism) already entails the drive for conceptual mastery – a form of knowing that would obtain and manipulate what it knows. Heidegger’s notion (indicated in his diaries recently published) that the clearing of Being could be equated with the “inner truth and greatness” of the Nazi movement indicates the perversity underlying his thought. He is (another) proof that the attempt to keep open the distinction between Being and beings (hysteria), or between the “that” of Being (or in the case of Aquinas the “that” (res significata) of God’s existence) and the “how” (modus significandi) is an impossibility.

Karl Barth’s theology shares with Heidegger the move against onto-theology and yet, Barth saw early on in Heidegger the danger in his historical form of thinking.   Barth would persistently refuse Bultmann’s attempt to bring Heidegger and Barth together, and of course Barth’s prescience was to recognize in Heidegger the embodiment of a form of thought he would call the anti-Christ.

The question is if Barth, much like Heidegger, was implicated in the very form of thought he was attempting to overcome. Barth marks his own theological turn against Aquinas and the analogia entis with his discovery of Anselm. The indication that even when he recognizes the inadequacy of a dialectical theology he fails to escape it is found in a reading of Romans from which he will not depart. When he turns to Romans 7:7ff he reads it, as Žižek does, as the dialectic constituting the normal Christian life. Hysteria and the dialectic with perversion is as far as Romans 7:7ff takes us. Balthasar’s recognition that Catholic thought needs, in part, the corrective that Barth brings and that Barth can be made to fit within Catholic thought indicates that the dialectic pendulum between perversion and hysteria keeps swinging.

It is not until Romans 8 that Paul introduces the Christian alternative to the agonistic dialectic of the non-Christian form of thought. “ For God has done what the law, weakened by the flesh, could not do: by sending his own Son in the likeness of sinful flesh, and to deal with sin, he condemned sin in the flesh, so that the just requirement of the law might be fulfilled in us, who walk not according to the flesh but according to the Spirit” (Romans 8:3-4).

He is risen and this constitutes a completely new form of thought – a post-Easter explanation and blog.

 

Advertisements

WALKING PHILOSOPHY

Walking Philosophy

Photo0062

The peripatetic stage in our life comes with the emptying out of the nest so that we have no destination, no particular urgency in the walking, and nothing other than the pleasure of one another’s company and conversation. We have done the running, but life returns us to learning to walk. 

The original Peripatetics walked with Aristotle and the walking, observing, and first order experience of Athens and its surroundings marked a departure from Plato’s static, otherworldly, forms. Plato, the broad shouldered, thick necked, sumo wrestler of a philosopher was all about remaining stationary, and through the Socratic dialogues the goal was to pin down one’s opponents. Aristotle’s philosophy is more about motion and less about standing firm. His is an exploratory, taking in the sights kind of philosophy. Peripatetic thought marks a form of thinking that accounts for the earth and mortality. Where Plato was dependent on the immortal soul’s ability to escape the body so as to arrive at the forms, the walking philosophers presume to find the forms in the walk.  

It is the pleasure of the walk, taking in the sights, and allowing the natural environment to dictate the form, or lack thereof, of thought that marks our perambulating. For us, games and sports have never proven conducive to promoting this pleasure, mainly because they are both things which one wins by making the other lose. Monopoly, one of my favorite board games from childhood, does not produce pleasure in the others company so much as pleasure at taking her company and property – which never made for great harmony. Games are often an extension of work, at which one is trying to get ahead – get all the cash. I’m not sure one can either be a success or a failure at walking. Walking is not a competitive sport, at least the kind of walking we do. We can’t criticize one another’s walking, but we can walk together – and in the walking we discover what presents itself and we are present to take it in.  

The walking philosophers and thinkers – Aristotle, Kant, Nietzsche, Wittgenstein, Rousseau, Heidegger and Thoreau – represent no particular school of thought other than their departure from an established static order. Kant, whose walks were so regular (perhaps a hint of transcendentalism even here) that townsfolk claimed they could set their clocks by his passing, is very different in his thought and walks than Nietzsche, who ascends and descends the heights in a desperate need to walk so as to think and to rid himself of excruciating pain.  

Thoreau and Rousseau would both walk into the wild but Thoreau revels in the solitude while Rousseau seems, even in his rejection of society to be desperately in need of it. His philosophy is the record of a man trying to make a departure from society, and perhaps in the final stage of life when he gives up on all social conquests, when the walking becomes an end in itself, he succeeds. Ironically, it is Rousseau’s influence through which the American transcendentalists seem to have filtered their very ‘American’ sense of nature, taken up in Thoreau’s Walking. 
wittgenstein-and-skinner-in-cambridge

Wittgenstein is at once the most solitary and social of walkers – as exacting in his solitude as he is solicitous and frustrating in his social relations. His students, perhaps, failed to understand the point of the walk and the sometimes wandering nature of the conversation. His comments on the colors reflected in the wet pavement, remarked on by Drury as if they must bear some weight, are simply part of the form of life encountered in the walk. Wittgenstein’s binding of soul to body means that walking, as well as words, exercises the soul. The words do not bear any peculiar weight but the form of life which occasions them do.  

It was for this reason that he did not want students to take notes during his lectures. Few of his students could find the point in his lectures as they were a performance of a form of life or a game for which their Platonic imaginations were unprepared. The boring, plodding work of definition and description was a first order work of philosophy that had already commenced and was being demonstrated, yet they were looking for some further point beyond the words.

heidegger

Though Heidegger sets forth his thought in an imaginary walk in ‘Country Path Conversations’ his notion that ‘I will non-willing’ poses the question if he had enough will to propel him down a path of his choosing. Authenticity in Being and Time is commonly interpreted in terms of willful commitment and “resoluteness” (Entschlossenheit) in the face of one’s own death but is, by the late 1930s, reintroduced in terms of Gelassenheit, as a nonwillful way of dwelling that is open to the enigmatic emerging forth of beings, an openness that “lets being be.”

Heidegger, in Simon Critchley’s description, expresses a very similar idea to Wittgenstein in his notion of Dasein:

“If the human being is really being-in-the-world, then this entails that the world itself is part of the fundamental constitution of what it means to be human. That is to say, I am not a free-floating self or ego facing a world of objects that stands over against me. Rather, for Heidegger, I am my world. The world is part and parcel of my being, of the fabric of my existence. We might capture the sense of Heidegger’s thought here by thinking of Dasein not as a subject distinct from a world of objects, but as an experience of openedness where my being and that of the world are not distinguished for the most part. I am completely fascinated and absorbed by my world, not cut off from it in some sort of ‘mind’ or what Heidegger calls ‘the cabinet of consciousness.’”[1]

Heidegger’s earthyness goes to the extreme and serves as a warning. His walks in the black forest would have been nicely off-set by a walk in Sherwood Forest or Yosemite, but the blood and soil of Germany dictate to him so that he becomes absorbed by the Dasein of the times. His support of the Nazi’s, to whatever extent, seems an inevitability of his philosophy. Habermas explains that his giving himself over to Dasein meant there was no room for criticism of Hitler and the Nazis: ‘[H]e detaches his actions and statements altogether from himself as an empirical person and attributes them to a fate for which one cannot be held responsible.’[2] The degree to which there is a reduction of nature or a reduction to nature is the problem of phenomenology but what the phenomenologists fail to account for is the ability to transmutate Dasein into a ‘fate’ that is pure evil.

Each of the peripatetic philosophers discovers a road, a form of thought grounded in earthly presence. This does not make them equal but the point of departure in each case seems to take in the reality of embodiment. The problem is that a philosophy grounded in embodiment would give itself over to the flesh – giving us Nazi philosophy. What is needed is an embodiment that allows for volition and freedom.

[1] Simon Critchley, ‘Being and Time, part 3: Being-in-the-world’ guardian.co.uk, 22 June 2009

[2] Jürgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures,(Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press ,1985). p. 156.